THE APPARENTLY MARGINAL ACTIVITIES OF MARCEL DUCHAMP
By Elena Filipovic
ISBN 978-0-262-034821-1
MIT Press £29.95
reviewed by Alan Dent

In her introduction , Filipovic points to the Duchamp’s
conventional beginnings as an artist. Had he continued as he began,
she suggests, his name might well be more or less forgotten. It
would be unworthy to suggest that such a principled artist
might have broken with his initial predictability in pursuit
of fame, but might it be that the marginal activities of the title
appealed to him partly because he knew the established art world is
a milling machine which grinds out a majority of more or less
indistinguishable artists and permits a very few to escape what
E.P.Thompson called, in a different context, the condescension of
posterity ?
Nu descendant un
escalier, his 1912 canvas rejected for exhibition by his fellow
cubists is an accomplished
but derivative work. Notwithstanding Douglas Cooper’s
division of Cubism into three phases, the latter enduring till 1921,
by 1912, Picasso and Braque had completed the pioneering work.
Les Demoiselles d’Avignon
is sometimes cited as the first proto-cubist painting. Whether or
not that view can be upheld, it unquestionably broke with the
tradition of western art. There is no absolute reason why, from that
innovation, Picasso was bound to move on to what came to be called
Cubism, but in retrospect it looks feasible that the breakthrough he
made in 1907 drove him to follow to its conclusion what he’d begun.
Nothing touching that could be said of Duchamp’s rejected painting.
From the perspective of the upheaval of the previous five years, it
looks like the work of a follower. Did Duchamp paint it in the
belief he could join the Cubist fraternity and by so doing win an
enduring place ? Did its rejection pull him up short and shock him
into the recognition that he was secondary, a peripheral epigone ?
In any case, it seems that it was shortly after what must have been
this painful experience that Duchamp began to ask the truly radical
questions about art which have made him, in Filipovic’s view, the
most significant artist of the modern world, and if that judgement
is questioned, certainly one of the most discussed.
Perhaps his disappointment in being turned down by the
movement whose great practitioners he was imitating, elicited that
questioning response which always arises when people’s fond
expectations are shattered. He began to think about the way the art
world works; to doubt the procedures by which a work of art is
granted its status as such. In 1913, he scribbled a note to himself:
“Can works be made which are not ‘of art’?” Why would an artist want
to remove the art from his works ? Was it because he saw the naked
emperor ? Did he realize that the paraphernalia of the art world:
galleries, agents, museums, curators, grants, judges, prizes,
conferred validity ? That is, what is marginal and secondary
dominates the primary ? Detaching the work from the world of art,
from the people who lived off art but didn’t produce any, from the
unoriginal minds which lived parasitically on genius, was a way of
asserting the primacy of the artist as creator. Yet Duchamp couldn’t
do this if he produced conventional canvases to be hung in galleries
and museums. He had to subvert all expectations. He needed to find a
way to protect originality by seeming to deny it.
Thus, the marginal activities of the title are those which
surround art but aren’t primary. They are merely apparently marginal
in Duchamp’s work because through his boxes, the large glass and the
secretly assembled Etant Données and similar projects he found a way
to wrest the work from the art world. Doubtless they constitute art,
in the sense of being designedly structured to engage with reality
in and through his sensibility, intelligence and skill. Yet they
escape from art as conceived of as an activity mediated by a system
which requires the attention of curators, dealers, museum directors
and so on. Filipovic makes clear that Duchamp by no means abandoned
art. He was highly productive. Nor did his declaration that he would
exhibit nothing lead to his absence from museums. This might look
like hypocrisy or a pose but as she argues, it is his exploration of
what he called the inframince,
the minute difference between an original and a copy and his
consequent questioning of what she likes to call the “auratic”, that
is crucial. His works are in museums but their status is quite
different from that of a conventional painting or sculpture by
virtue of being self-conscious: they know they are art. This knowing
is part of the way they have been put together. As she argues, what
Duchamp is always aware of is “the question of the apparatuses for
the legitimation, valuation and circulation of the artwork”. He is
trying to make work which reveals that awareness.
Inevitably, she has to touch on the relationship of Duchamp
to Broodthaers who, of course, kicked off his successful trajectory
after years of neglect and poverty as a poet through an act of
insincerity. He turned the art establishment’s emptiness against
itself; the activities of the structures which mediate art have
nothing in common with the motivations and procedures of artists. By
renouncing the latter and pandering to the former, he found the
acceptance and the money which had been denied him.
Benjamin H.D. Buchloh believed Broodthaers had succeeded
where Duchamp failed and Eva Krauss asserted he was “calling
attention to the supposedly neutral containers of culture and
questioning this putative neutrality”. Filipovic, while granting
Broodthaers his seminal place in the creation of Institutional
Critique, is sceptical of those commentators who have failed to see
that the subversive activities they praise Broodthaers for are just
as present in the work
by Duchamp which they ignore or play down. She argues that even
today, in discussions of Institutional Critique, Duchamp’s major
work is treated as if it doesn’t exist.
Clement Greenberg remarked that Duchamp “locked
advanced-advanced art into what has amounted to hardly more than
elaborations, variations on and recapitulations of his original
ideas.”Filipovic wants to rescue her subject from such dismissal and
to propose that Etant Données
far from being a mere rehearsing of old tropes, was a late act of
radicalism as potent, beneath its “crass and incongruous
hyperrealism”, as anything he produced.
Perhaps what this fascinating study brings to the fore is the
forever curious social status of art; all art, not merely the
visual. What artists are up to, painting, sculpting, composing,
writing, filming, choreographing, is always tangential to any
society’s principal activities and its view of itself. There have
been slave societies, feudal societies, capitalist societies,
totalitarian societies of various degrees of nastiness even
hunter-gatherer societies where you might expect artistic activities
to be relatively integrated; but there has never been an artistic
society.
Our culture is soaked in entertainment, which is debased art.
People who would never listen to Bach are blithely unaware that
without him there would be no Kylie Minogue, just as they ignore
that without Aeschylus there would be no television mini-series. Art
is kept at arm’s length by the majority who prefer its downgraded
offshoot. The pull of
our culture is to money. The impulse of art is to truth, as
definitively as that of
science. What Duchamp did was to wrest art away from those who
package it. In doing so he foregrounded the perilous, odd, marginal,
precarious, status of the artist. Thanks to him, it is now taken for
granted in the visual arts that conventional means of presentation
can be radically upended. When will we see the same in, say,
literature and theatre ? If the art works doesn’t need the museum,
why does the play need the theatre ? There’s the kind of question,
at the core of Duchamp’s effort, which sends shivers down the spines
of arts administrators, producers, managers, agents, publishers; the
bevvy of those who, in vulgar and unkind parlance are sometimes
referred to as the pimps of the artistic world.
|