THE
GREAT GUIDE:
What David Hume Can Teach Us about Being Human and Living Well
Julian Baggini
ISBN 978-0-691-20543-4
Hume was a racist who expressed the view
coloured people must be inferior as they produced
collectively no great civilisations nor individually any great
intellectual accomplishments. He was upbraided for his sloppy
thinking in this regard by his contemporary James Beattie, who
unfortunately, in a weighty tome, dismissed the entirety of his
work. It’s worth bearing this bad mistake and poor thinking by Hume
in mind as it illustrates two of his cautions: avoid extremes and
stick to the evidence, and don’t slavishly accept the ideas of even
the best thinkers.
Though he wrongly thought white people superior, he would never have
advocated cruelty or exploitation of their putative inferiors. On
the contrary, it’s probable, had he elaborated ideas about how white
people should behave, he’d have exhorted them to kindness towards
those less fortunate. Hume made a mistake in thinking but he had
nothing of the KKK or the EDL about him. He recognised that our
emotions are a “great guide” and that human sympathy is universal.
Logic, Hume spotted, tells us nothing about how the world functions.
This is part of what makes him so distinct from many philosophers.
In a sense, he dispenses with philosophy and plumps instead for
thinking. As Baggini says, he cut philosophy down to size in the
Treatise of Human Nature (1739-1740) by insisting on the
limits of human understanding. His effort was always to stay within
the limits nature has prescribed. No point railing against the
facts. We haven’t been granted total lucidity and it does violence
to our nature to pretend we have. Hume is the enemy of hubris. What
might he make of those who suggest we should colonise other planets
when we have finally made this one uninhabitable? Perhaps he would
have seen it as an example of the unfortunate human inclination to
believe our possibilities are endless.
Hume identified two fundamental forms of thinking: about ideas and
about facts. The first is purely abstract, the second requires
experience. All Ps are Qs but not all Qs are Ps can be grasped
without any experience of the world;
all apples are fruit but not all fruit is apples requires
knowing what an apple is, and that can’t be done purely abstractly.
Anyone who has sat in a philosophy seminar while the tutor asks how
we can know the table our files rest on exists, will find Hume
congenial. There can be no abstract, absolute certainty about the
world of reality we inhabit; we have to accept experience and to
begin our thinking from it.
Ethics, in Hume’s conception, is a matter of what is agreeable or
useful to ourselves and others. Obviously, that implies we must
avoid absolutes. Everything is a matter of degree. Hume roots ethics
in circumstance, the only sensible procedure. Interestingly, that
makes him dissolve the distinction between voluntary and involuntary
vice or virtue. The judgement as to whether an action is vicious
depends on how agreeable or useful it is, not on intentionality.
This begs the question of how we should respond to unintentionally
harmful actions. For example, drivers of diesel vehicles may not
intend to harm the respiratory systems of children, but if they do,
is that a vice? In Hume’s view, yes. We inhabit a culture where
conscious intention is taken to be the hallmark of vice or virtue.
The law insists on intent to establish guilt in certain crimes, even
the most serious . The Freudian notion of unconscious motivation has
engendered a belief that attributing guilt to those suffering from
putative neuroses or disorders is misplaced. Surely Hume is right:
even if an action is performed with complete unawareness of its
negative consequences, if they follow, the action is a vice. That
doesn’t imply punishment, of course; but it does suggest correction,
whether by education, admonition, explanation or some other benign
form.
The famous problem of induction is Hume’s argument that the past
can’t predict the future. No matter how many times we heat water at
sea level and measure its boiling point, we can’t prove the same
result will prevail in the future. We assume it will, but that is a
matter of experience. In this way, Hume recognizes the limits of our
understanding. A kindred point is made by the billiard ball example:
purely by thinking, it’s impossible to predict what will happen when
one billiard ball hits another. The cue might return to its original
position, both balls might shatter into pieces, the target ball
might fly off the table. Without experience we can’t know, but from
experience we can take measurements, start thinking and work out how
to win snooker matches.
Is thinking the same as reasoning? Baggini makes a distinction
between reason and logic but perhaps the latter is a better term for
establishing the difference between purely abstract thinking and
thinking which flows from experience. Hume exhorts us to “reason”
modestly. He recommends scepticism even about our doubts, yet he’s
no Pyrrhonist. Their unwillingness to draw any conclusion leads to
stasis. We have to draw hedged conclusions and avoid dogmatism.
“Nature” he says “is too strong for principle.” By this he doesn’t
mean we shouldn’t embrace values nor stick by them, but they should
be grounded in experience. “A wise man will proportion his belief to
the evidence.” That’s not to say, don’t have beliefs. It’s perfectly
sensible to believe global warming is leading to climate change and
to campaign for serious action. It’s attention to the evidence which
matters.
In the deterministic universe revealed by science ( in Hume’s time
there were no scientists, they were natural philosophers; the term
scientist was coined in 1833) is there such a thing as chance? Hume
believed it was merely apparent: behind all seeming randomness was
an unseen determinism. The argument goes on, as it has since the
dispute between Bohr and Einstein. Baggini identifies the other
meaning of chance: that things happen to us through no fault of our
own. Misfortune is often not deserved and by implication therefore,
neither is good fortune. Hume has bad news for the rich: their
wealth is largely a matter of luck. You might say he believed he
lived in a luckocracy. The important conclusion he draws is that
people overestimate their merit and underestimate their luck. Would
he have mocked the notion of “meritocracy”? Employed as a serious
political doctrine, the term began, of course, in satire. Hume would
almost certainly have identified with the latter. The notion that
the distribution of wealth and income fits neatly some alleged
distribution of whatever “merit” is supposed to mean is risible.
Hume’s view reminds us to avoid an arrogant assumption of our right
to good fortune and to see the misfortune of others as something we
should have sympathy for and which might befall us. He was long
dead, of course, before a politics of equality was elaborated, but
it’s probable he’d have supported measures to attenuate poverty and
to reduce the discrepancy between the rich and the rest without
embracing any self-defeating dogma.
As a determinist, Hume has no belief in absolute free will. He makes
a distinction between “liberty of spontaneity” and “liberty of
indifference”: the former is merely the ability act without
restraint from any outside agency, the latter is the capacity to act
outside cause and effect, an impossibility. Thus, how can we be held
responsible? If Hume is right, wasn’t Hitler fated to create the
Jewish genocide? Ironically, Hume arrives at the opposite
conclusion: “Where would be the foundation of morals, if particular
characters had no certain and determinate power to produce
particular sentiments, and if these sentiments had no constant
operation on actions.” What this implies is that our motives impinge
on our behaviour in a regular manner. It’s when we are capricious
that we deny this. Caligula, Hitler, Stalin, any tyrant you care to
mention are characterised by capricious behaviour; it is almost a
hallmark of tyranny. Hume sees our moral sentiments as arising from
our nature, part of our biological inheritance. The implication is
that though there are variations, there is an underlying constancy
(what you might call a universal morality). He has confidence in our
moral sentiments. When we diverge from them in ways which appear
unruly or whimsical, we recognise something is wrong. Of course,
this can suggest there is a “normality” and anything which doesn’t
fit is a deviation. This is essentially Hume’s position: just as
it’s our nature to have two arms and legs, so it is to have shared
moral sentiments. Does this imply discrimination against
“difference”? Not at all. The prevalent contemporary view (usually
typified as post-modernism) that there is nothing but difference, no
given regularities is obviously tendentious. At the very core of
Hume’s philosophy is the acceptance of the regularities of nature.
It is through them, through our experience of them and our thinking
about them that most of our knowledge is derived.
His critics have picked up on what might be an unfortunate
formulation: that we are “nothing but a bundle or collection of
different perceptions.” As Baggini points out, the universe is,
looked at reductively, nothing but a collection of atoms. That our
bundle or collection produces language, maths, science, Shakespeare,
Beethoven, Frida Kahlo and Jane Austen is more aw-inspiring than the
notion of some indefinable spirit which putatively provides our
creative faculties. The formula is connected to Hume’s difficulty
with the idea of self; Baggini points up the similarity of his view
to that of Buddhism: self is a delusion. Antonio Damasio in Self
Comes to Mind tries to show how the brain establishes an
enduring sense of self. The attempt is partly successful, which
probably illustrates Hume’s principle of the restricted scope of
human cognition; but what Damasio and neuroscientists like him can
establish is that the sustained sense of self is not an illusion. It
does depend on the firing of particular neurons in particular
patterns, and when disease disrupts, the sense of self can be lost;
but it is real:
our brains are set up to create a continuous sense of
biography, even if we are ultimately no more than a bundle of
perceptions.
Perhaps Hume’s history of Great Britain was a distraction from his
major work in philosophy, but it permitted an important insight. As
Baggini puts it: “History is a means to discover what is constant
and unchanging in human nature and what is subject to alteration.”
To discover this distinction is crucial. It is, in a sense, what
Hume’s philosophy is driving at. What is unchanging we can define as
human nature. What is subject to alteration as cultural. Defining
the former permits us to dismiss many misconceptions, the idea that
white people are superior for example. Hume’s view that our
knowledge derives from experience of the regularities of nature
suggest that our brains are wired to pick up on the regularities.
Perhaps we are predisposed to compute statistical regularities in
the environment (physical and social) and impelled to compliance (in
a descriptive sense). That might make sense given that whatever
looms large in the environment could have significant survival
advantages or disadvantages. Hume suggests this may be the way our
minds (brains) work. If so, then the second dimension ie the
impelling towards compliance might be crucial. It could help to
explain, for example, why deprived circumstances are so difficult to
escape from: if the brain computes the statistical regularities in
an environment typified by poverty and its attendant ills and impels
towards compliance, it could make a conscious effort to escape those
circumstances very difficult.
Unity and variety might appear contradictory, but Hume recognises
that great variety is not only compatible with universal endowment,
but intrinsic to it. Perhaps language provides an example: out of
Universal Grammar come the six thousand languages, or so, of today.
It’s in the nature of the language faculty to provide this variety;
the security of the faculty, as it were, makes the huge variety of
the infinity of possible sentences no kind of threat to unity, but
rather a necessity. If there were only one language, it wouldn’t be
language but grunts. Language is, by definition various and produces
an infinite array of sentences.
There’s a nice story in Hume’s The Natural History of Religion
which pokes fun at Catholicism: when the convert who has taken
communion which Catholics believe to be the body and blood of Christ
is asked the next day how many gods there are replies there are none
because he has been told there is only one and he ate him the day
before. Hume viewed religion as essentially superstition, but he
avoided intolerance or bigotry. Rather he took a tolerant attitude
while sticking to his guns.
The Francophile Hume was well-received in France. He had something
in common with the philosophes and was friendly, for a time,
with Rousseau but finally viewed him negatively. That an easy-going
and cheerful person like Hume should clash with a paranoid egoist
like Rousseau is hardly surprising. What is interesting
philosophically, is the question of emotion. Rousseau seemed to put
his trust in it. Hume too expressed the view that reason alone was
no guide. Doesn’t the fact
that it led Rousseau to his poor treatment of Hume suggest he was
wrong? As Baggini explains, Hume’s position is subtle and balanced:
ethics must embrace human nature and we are composed of reason and
emotion. In this regard, Damasio is worth referring to once more.
His exploration of the case of Phineas Gage who suffered serious
brain damage in a dynamiting accident on the US railway shows that
the previously upright, hard-working, responsible, charming Gage,
became a foul-mouthed waster when the part of his brain responsible
for emotion was blasted, while his intellectual faculties remained
intact. Perhaps the case could be interpreted as a vindication of
Hume’s faith in the rational role of emotion.
Baggini is forgiving of some of Hume’s wayward views about women. He
praises him for having adumbrated today’s evolutionary psychologists
in arguing that infidelity in women should be treated more harshly
than in men as a man needs to be sure the offspring he is bringing
up are his own. The argument is flawed. We know of cultures where
the reproductive function of sex was unknown and in consequence the
men responsible for bringing up children were the mother’s brothers.
The dual-standard has nothing to do with men needing to know the
offspring they labour for are there own and everything to do with
conquest, control, the intrusion of economic and social class, the
concentration of power and the need to pass on wealth in the male
line. Baggini is here a little to quick to grant Hume’s genius and a
little too slow to recognise that genius has its limits.
Superstition and enthusiasm were Hume’s bugbears: “Nor does the wolf
molest more the timid flock, than superstition does the anxious
breast of wretched mortals.” He saw the first as the asylum of the
wretched ( an idea Marx picked up on) and the latter as the bane of
society. Both were rooted in ignorance. Here he looks to be astute.
His enthusiasm is what today we might term fanaticism or
fundamentalism. The world is beset by fanatics of one sort or
another: communists, neo-liberals, Jihadists, Zionists, white
supremacists, extreme nationalists. What is lacking is Hume’s
middle-way, his willingness to accept the limits of our thinking and
his insistence that our ideas, feelings and practices must be in
keeping with the way nature has made us. A fanatic is someone who
insists on their position however much it may clash with the
evidence of our experience. “It is needless to push our researches
so far as to ask, why we have humanity or a fellow-feeling with
others,” writes Hume. Or to ask why we have one nose and two ears.
The fanatic is characterised by an inability to accept what we have
to take for granted and who insist on trying to force reality to fit
a pre-existing theoretical grid. Thus, the Zionist insists god gave
Palestine to Abraham when experience dictates such certainty is
impossible.
“’Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole
world to the scratching of my finger.” What Hume means by “reason”
here is logic whose purpose is to reveal what is contradictory or
impossible. Relying on logic alone divorces us from the feelings
which are part of our biological endowment and without which we
aren’t fully human. The formulation is pertinent to our condition:
we have arrived, through the application of logic, which is the
customary form of modern public debate, at the threat to our
survival from nuclear war or climate change. Hume recognises the
pre-eminent value of the softer emotions: “The merit of
BENEVOLENCE….the very softness and tenderness of the sentiment….its
engaging endearments….its fond expressions…its delicate
attentions…and all that flow of love and friendship…being delightful
in themselves are communicated to the spectators and melt them into
the same fondness and delicacy.” In contradistinction to this
acceptance of our nature, we have elaborated a prevailing ideology
which claiming hard-headedness (though it is soft-brained) rejects
everything which can’t be measured. It is a dangerously psychopathic
culture which elevates people like Donald Trump who are so far from
Hume’s wise man who will proportion his belief to the evidence they
can seriously suggest drinking disinfectant.
Hume takes what would be today an unfashionable view of aesthetics.
He questions the cliché that “beauty is in the eye of the beholder”:
“though this axiom, by passing into a proverb, seems to have
attained the sanction of common sense” he suggests an opposing form
ie that there are objective standards of judgement. As Baggini
explains, Hume would dismiss as ridiculous the idea that Salieri is
as good a composer as Mozart. Today, this judicious common sense has
all but evaporated under
pressure of the post-modern insistence on extreme
subjectivity: if I prefer Donny Osmond to Mozart, then who is to say
the latter is a better composer? That this empty- headed idiocy is
embraced by intellectuals is a measure of how distorted and
denatured our culture has become through its manic pursuit of lucre.
Hume accepts taste, but he refuses the extreme view which proposes
taste does not need to rely on some quality in the appreciated
object: “there are certain qualities in objects which are fitted by
nature to produce …particular feelings.” Of course, people can
always impersonate genuine response. For whatever is genuine in
human feeling, there is a phoney counterpart. Also, people can
confuse realms: they can, for example, listen through rather than to
music, using it as a means of group identification or putative sign
of certain inner qualities, just as they can read through
literature, which accounts for the huge sales of trash like Fifty
Shades of Grey and the utter of obscurity of some supremely good
prose writers.
Hume isn’t suggesting a single response, a kind of aesthetic
totalitarianism. He recognises there will be difference of emphasis
due to a variety of factors and inevitable debate; yet his position
rejects the modern collapse into “anything goes and nothing
matters”; a view, of course, which serves to suggest moral
judgements are also utterly subjective: if there is nothing but
subjectivity, why shouldn’t people be reduced to technological ants,
made mere servants of the economic machine geared to the interests
of the rich? It’s easy to see why Hume’s insistence on a given
universal human nature from which our moral sentiments arise is
barely present in contemporary political debate.
Hume may not be an infallible guide (he would surely have scoffed at
the possibility) but the essence of his work, the argument that
humans everywhere and always display moral sentiments, that these
must arise from our given nature, that our emotions are
indispensable in telling us how to act and that experience is the
source of most of our knowledge make him an indispensable thinker.
Baggini knows his subject thoroughly, explains his work in clear
prose and adds biographical detail which is as illuminating as it is
interesting. Perhaps we could even hope that a few of our venerated
leaders might spend a bit of time with Hume. It might make them
slightly more congenial, and even save us from annihilation.
|