NOUGHTOCRACY
Chevengur by Andrey Platonov
Harvill
Secker, 2023
ISBN
978-1-843-43152-7
“A
fierce sun of arid knowledge had
risen
over their feelings”
[1]
Perhaps
it comes as no surprise, today, that we have come full circle; at least if the
starting point is the rise of a unilinear scientific socialism as it cast its
shadow over utopian yearning and as it coincided with what Jean-Pierre Voyer
described as the “achieved opposition between the life of the individual and the
life of the species.”[2]
Now, the very idea of Revolution, in the West at least, is as utopian as the
wild yet misunderstood imaginings of Fourier and any identification with the
species-being has more than been severed. It is being actively necrophilised not
just by artificial intelligence but by the historically planned and militarised
ethnocide in Palestine and environs. So why return to the past to seek hope,
theoretical succour and
escapist pleasure in a novel from late 20s Soviet Union? Because the
character’s in Platonov’s Chevengur have set out to find each other, find
a new way of being-together, to find a form of communism at a time when it had
already been internationally declared despite its ongoing assault on dissidents
(Kronstadt Soviet, Makhnovists, Left Opposition etc.) and despite the
reintroduction, from 1921, of brazen capitalist methods under the auspices of
the New Economic Policy. No wonder, then, that Platonov, a land-engineer, solar
power seer and inventor of a photo-electric-resonator-transformer (563), a more
or less written-out writer during his lifetime, received, in the marginalia of
one of his manuscripts, the epithet “bastard” from none other than Stalin.
Errancy
A
Don Quixote or a Ulysses of the Revolution? This seems to be the
common literary touchstone when coming to this novel. But we have here something
of an anti-classic, a novel that eschews not only the cleanliness of authorised
thought, but also a social realism that, while seeming to depict “objective
conditions” only served to occlude what lies deeper than such a constructed
reality: the materiality of feelings and imaginings, an affecting social
imaginary that undermines naturalistic certainties and those as-the-crow-flies
categories that act as modes of separation and give rise to rackets that each
proffer up their own ideological justifications.[3]
So, not only are Platonov’s characters wandering through the steppes (the
character Kopionkin rides a horse called “strength of the proletariat”) and away
from crowded settlements be they villages or cities, but their minds wander away
from the givens of work and politics. They wander away from the orthodoxies of
state capitalist communism as well as from bourgeois common sense with all its
empirical interests and moral judgmentalism. This errancy of movement and
thought in Chevengur seems at the same turn to embrace the Revolution and
to denounce it, to greet it with full flushed fanfare as well as offer it a
satirical eulogy. The creative
life-blood of the revolution itself is what is sought after, or should we
more accurately say, as Platonov critically implies, the characters are looking
for a beyond of that communism that the Revolution has purportedly already
brought about. Yet do the literary means, or should we say the sensibility
articulated by Platonov in this novel, amount to what Tara Lane describes as
“absurdist, grotesque and phantasmagorical?”[4]
There is an element of these in Chevengur, but this may be to hide the
novel behind a literary-philologic partition, rather than leading us to an
appraisal of a work that, being much more than a novel, seeks to engage us in an
ontology of communism.
In the
first chapter of her book Tara Lane draws attention to how Platonov was at odds
to contemporaneously prevailing notions of proletarian art. Key, for her, is
Platonov’s rejection of aesthetic beauty; even, we could say, the cruel beauty
of an ideologically motivated or propagandist depiction of “objective
conditions” whose remnants still exert a fascination today. In her scene-setting
appraisal of Platonov she enters into a discussion of how he polemically
embraced the ‘ugly’; but this is an ugly that for her, via the Russian word
bezobraznyi, entails formlessness in that for Platonov, proletarian art, in
being unforeseen and without an a priori image, fruitfully lacked a
canonical model through which to appear. For Platonov, the proletarians he has
in mind are seen, like his own self depiction, as “insignificant outsiders.”
They are not the cultural workers of the Writers Union or LEF, but those who
turn towards the making of objects and artefacts that bear no relation to art
history. Maybe Platonov has in mind something erroneous, something akin to what
came to be known as outsider art in that, as Lane suggests, such a practice, far
from artistic expertise, entails “utter vulnerability”, the “abject” and the
“abominable.”[5]
We are perhaps, through these musings, in the realm of a kind of bricolage of
the Levi-Strauss type: “A water-cooled machine gun, attached to a cast iron pot,
became a system for the production of moonshine.” (131) These are artefacts,
assemblages, that, as one character in the novel suggests, can “touch any heart
and make a man better and kinder.” (11) Whilst this raises notions of the social
purpose of productive labour and the decommodification of the art object, it
also hints at the hidden
sensual labour in any product; a communicated sensuality that could
undermine the phantasmagoria of commodity objects. But, returning to Lane, such
a messthetics, a unique and ‘ugly’ conjuncture of oddments, not only undermines
the notion of the reproductability of moulds or models, it acts as a herald of
an unseen and singularising proletarian art that finds its personification in
the ‘doings’ of Platonov’s characters. They seek communism because, even in the
Soviet Union, there is no satisfactory image of it that could (ever) appease
their utopian longings. That is unless the mystery object that falls from the
sky (“a long piece of trimmed stone”) offers an enigmatic satisfaction as it is
gradually decided by the assembled and perplexed characters that the mystery
object – a readymade transforming before their eyes? –
is in fact a manufactured barrel. (318)
Finding
Chevengur
Perhaps
the errant dreamers of Chevengur are wandering with more than just
directionless hope. Maybe these characters are aware, or intuit, that communes
like Chevengur are more widespread than was common knowledge at the time. Maybe,
to reuse and redeploy Marx’s phrase, they were convinced that more than just one
“localised microcosmos” was in existence. Richard Stites bears this out when he
writes: “Commune signs bearing such designations as Brotherhood, Will, Hope,
Paradise, Proletarian, Karl Marx, Lenin, Rosa Luxemburg, Hammer, Red Orphan,
Paris Commune, Anthill, and Free World began to adorn a countryside that was
unused-to signs or names.”[6]
Maybe, with the fictional creation of Chevengur, Platonov is not just drawing on
his own experiences as a jobbing land-engineer, but is re-raising the spectre of
the Russian Populists (The Peoples Will), for whom the Rural Commune (Obshchina,
Mir, Artel) could, with its basis in communal ownership and peasant
assemblies, be a grounded paradigm for a coming communism. In the last decade of
his life Marx thoroughly studied this possibility and in one of four drafts of a
letter to Vera Zasulich he wrote: “It [the ‘Rural Commune’] may thus become the
direct starting point of the economic system towards which modern society
is tending; it may open a new chapter that does not begin with its own suicide.”[7]
This ‘suicide’, or “harsh tribute” as Marx less emotively writes in an
alternative draft, is the prevailing scientific socialist idea that a
predominantly rural Russia had to pass through the rapacious and dispossessing
capitalist mode of production (as a ‘developmental stage’) to achieve communism,
when, as Populists like Chernychevsky offered, communism’s basis in the rural
commune could lead, as Jacques Camatte phrases it, to a “leaping of the CMP.”[8]
This leap, “passing over the intermediate logical moments,”[9]
was widely debated amongst revolutionaries in the late 19th Century.
Rosa Luxemburg, whilst not adhering to this thesis, referred to it as a
“scepticism regarding the possibilities of capitalist development in Russia...”
[10] This is, in a sense, what Platonov is
surrealistically circling in Chevengur. Moreover, he is, as we will soon
see, inferring, through his fiction, what Camatte would write many years later:
“[…] if classes had produced the state in the West, in Russia the state produced
the classes.”[11]
“Summon
the poor to Chevengur” declares a character. (307) Here, using layers of irony,
Platonov, as is the unrealistic wont of fiction, passes over the intermediate
logical moments and not only abandons the social realism of the official Soviet
line, but reveals it as an ideological ruse. Having his characters believe they
have brought about communism, as if by an unspoken and tacit declaration or in
the shadow of a mutual delusion, Platonov brings to light the contentious point
that, in a vastly rural country, the proletariat had to be brought into
existence as a social force by the Bolshevik state.[12]
The Chevengurians have instaurated communism without this proletariat, they have
either responded-to or overcome the “objective conditions” as if by means of a
religio-magic and now need to evangelise: the object needs to find its subject,
the belief system needs its believers. However, there is a further irony in that
going to ‘summon the poor’ implies that the form of communism established in
Chevengur needs its content, and that the poor, rather than being seen as the
subject of the Revolution are dramatized as its obtainable object! This, then,
is a thinly veiled critique of the homogenising proletarian ideology of the
Soviet State, which, as Guy Debord suggested, turns the worker into a hollow
representation not a living representative. But there is a further twist. When
the poor arrive in Chevengur they are accompanied by “the others.” (330) Not
only is Platonov inferring that the proletariat is this ‘other,’ or that the
proletariat is indistinguishable from the amorphous others, he is showing us how
the albeit sincere Chevengurians of the RevCom are being confronted with the
revelation of their own inculcated mythic delusion. In this way he engages his
readers in an ontology of communism: their expectations dashed they nonetheless
offer Chevengur to this motley ghost-like crew of fellow wanderers. Migrants.
Nobodies. Barely bodied. Worn out. Spectres of economic abuse, a residual class,
the “others,” whoever they are, are welcomed. This, in a sense, uncannily echoes
Marx’s own views about the expansion and development of the Rural Commune away
from “natural kinship” by means of “undergoing contact with strangers.”[13]
Here Comes Anybody.
The
poor are summoned to Chevengur by means of a declaration which a character
writes out on a piece of linen using a coal from a nearby stove. The Declaration
reads: “COMRADES THE POOR. YOU HAVE MADE EVERY COMFORT AND THING IN THE WORLD.
NOW YOU HAVE DESTROYED THEM AND WANT SOMETHING BETTER – ONE ANOTHER. TO THIS
END, WE HERE IN CHEVENGUR SEEK TO ACQUIRE COMRADES FROM THE PASSING ROADS.”
(312) In appealing to the poor as comrades the Chevengurians (and by extension
Platonov) are muddying the water of the official ideology for whom the poor are
seen as exclusively proletarian and, less and less over the 1920s, as a
peasantry that came to be increasingly characterised as a “sign of backwardness
and stagnation, a reactionary mass.” By using the word ‘poor’ Platonov seems to
be suggesting that we go back to a time before the poor became classified as
either proletarians or peasants and in this way the poor are the “others” and
the others are the “nameless grassroots people” (320) who, perhaps, have become
a form of ‘bare life’,
a tabula rasa voided of ideology or mutated by ideologies that see them not as
heterogeneous “sensuous beings,” but as an abstract content to fill an
ideological form not of their own making. In this way Platonov touches upon
another aspect of the ontology of communism that seeks to resuscitate a
spirituality that does not take on a religious form but summons forth a psyche:
“Was the soul a pitiful heart, or a mind inside a man’s head?” (141) asks one
character and as Platonov has written elsewhere “the Bolsheviks had wanted to
replace the heart with the head” (534) and this crude dualism, this acceptance
of mutually reified meanings, left even the “ethereal world” (of the social
imaginary?) “empty and hopeless – even to the point of suicide.”[14]
What form could this spirituality take? There are many instances in Chevengur
when the very self-interrogation of the characters summons their psychical
dynamism, their own ‘othering’ as a form that spirituality can take after the
death of God. As another character offers: “The heart’s a landless peasant.”
(357)
These
‘others’, then, as “unknown designations” (336), fill the ever-vigilant
Chevengurians with an open-hearted inquisitiveness. They do not see their guests
as threatening Cossacks or marauding stragglers from the White Army, but as
uncategorisable people, as, perhaps, ‘species-beings’ or, in the parlance of the
Bordigist Left, a potential “party-community.” A lack of judgementalism enables
them to seek points of affective contact with the ‘others.’ There is a
warding-off of domination. As Platonov has Dvanov say: “[…] he had no
convictions so certain as to allow him to feel superior.” (440) Also, at play
here is that the ‘others’ are quickly related to as default orphans: “These
others had been born with no possibility of any gift […] Their parents had
conceived them not through surplus of body by through night time anguish […]
Each mother had disappeared […] so as not to see her child and inadvertently
start to love it forever.” (334) None of the Chevengurians speak of their
families or are depicted as belonging to distant families and so the family-form
seems not to exist in Chevengur. Except for the relationship between Dvanov and
his step-father (albeit not a blood-tie) families are depicted as sites of
conflict and abuse that inestimably damage the ‘vital force’ of children. So,
there is a pronounced warding-off of the family-form: “Once you start families
here, you’ll soon be breeding petty-bourgeois.” (380) An inference can be read
here as one that, whilst seeking to free children from parental domination, sees
the family as being isomorphic with domineering and guilt-inducing institutional
power as a whole.[15]
From this it follows that, in order for the orphans of Chevengur to make
themselves into “future person[s]”[16]
(334) adequate to communism and its beyond, rules of kinship and consanguinity
need to be abandoned to form a communism in which the oxymoronic greeting
“comrade other” (343) can take on a
totemic efficacy. As
Deleuze and Guattari have suggested the Oedipus complex, projected into the
family-form as its psycho-sexual disciplinary mechanism, is wielded in the West
as a “repressing-representation” of desire; a desire that could outstrip the
impulse control disorder of ego-centricity and become diffuse as “class
affection.” (309)
Organic
Intellectuals
If this
were a social realist novel then the meetings of the RevCom and the Marx Reading
Circle are where one would expect to hear the party line and the idealisms of
disembodied materialism, but in Chevengur these meetings, whilst
earnestly aspiring to what Lenin or some faceless super-ego expects, veer often
into farce and parody, a farce and parody that nevertheless expresses a serious
commitment to communism; but, it seems, a communism as set out for the
Chevengurians in the classic texts, posters and edicts from the Provincial
Capital. Despite their will to learn from such texts, it is this abstracted
communism that most of the characters, except for Prokofy who acts as their
translator, struggle to articulate amongst themselves; a struggle due to the
obstacle of their being organic auto-theorisers who are suspicious of a
monopolising intellectual class.[17]
For one character communism in its rhetorical form seems like “dead signs” (214)
and “mere words” (273), for another the term “objective conditions” is
reiterated obsessively as if it is more a sonorous spell or a tongue-twister
than a fragment of revolutionary theory. In the Marx Reading Circle, Chepurny
offers: “The man wrote and wrote […] but we’ve done everything first and read
about it afterward. He might as well not have written.” (289) Platonov, in
narrator mode, goes heretically further: “Karl Marx looked down from the walls
like an alien Sabaoth, and his terrifying books were unable to lead a man to any
reassuring imagination of communism.” (293) It is perhaps this imaginative edge,
this almost Fourierist poetic licence, that marks out the organic intellectuals
of Chevengur. Whilst Platonov, a practical man himself, is sympathetic to the
Chevengurian’s embracing of praxis, he also maintains a utopian edge: “The
Revolution had been hauled along by departments and institutions, as if the
apparatus of the State were a machine for the construction of socialism.” (209)
This avowed anti-statism is, in the context in which he was writing and until
this day, a utopian yearning and, as such, requires that, in defiance the of the
intellectual caste, we “unlearn letters” (164) or use words “to turn current
feelings into thoughts.” All Power to the social imaginary? All power to a
mixed-semiotic?
Signs
and Names
Perhaps, when Richard Stites suggests that the rural communities were not used
to seeing “signs and names” he is perhaps referring to a situation of illiteracy
amidst the peasant classes. One
could infer from his comment that the majority of communes were led by an exodus
from the urban centres. His own book refutes this inference in that as he
writes: “The dream of most peasants had always been and still remained in the
1920s to be left alone by the state, with all the land managed and rotated in
their own tradition of the mir-obshchina.”[18]
Whilst this state of affairs was brutally put down in the 1930s[19]
we have to remember that Platonov has not set his depiction of an experimental
community in an urban setting, but on the rural steppe. For Marx this divide
between city and countryside was a presupposition of modern capitalism and this
in turn made the Revolution urban-centric. Platonov’s Chevengur, then,
seems to synthesise these
separate spheres and embrace the
(utopian?) potential of “social recipocrity in differentiation,”[20]
that mutual interaction and inherence with ‘strangers’ could give rise to.[21]
So, in Chevengur we do not so much encounter philosophers as ponderers
and brooders (auto-theorists), we do not so much encounter writers as
reminiscers, we don’t hear dialectical reasoning but the unresolved provocations
of troubling dilemmas and, rather than peons to “luxurious Moscow art,” (xi) we
encounter plaintive and romantic depictions of nature. Crucial here in terms of
those “signs and names” that may be a marker of class divisions, is Platonov’s
description of an Esperanto-like or concrete poetry graphic that Dvanov draws in
response to a request to come up with a symbol for a monument: “The recumbent
figure eight denotes the eternity of time, which the upright double-ended arrow
denotes the infinity of space.” (160) This need for a symbol and its depiction
may well be intended by Platonov as a stimulating parody of the Hammer and
Sickle flag which came into existence in 1922. Digging in the nether regions of
Marx we can’t help suggesting that the symbol that Dvonov draws could well be
taken as the moniker of the ‘historic party.’[22]
Communism in its state-ideological form glorified the worker. To work was seen
as the meaning of life and to this end we are all familiar with the statues of
heroic workers and how this representation seemed hollow to the workers at
large. In Chevengur something very much counterpoised to this occurs:
“Only one thing was unclear: was labour still necessary under socialism – or
would nature, left to follow its own course, provide enough nourishment anyway?”
(332) Such discussions between characters abound in Chevengur to the
degree that the book reads at times like an anti-work manifesto, and at others
like a depiction of heaven on earth. At times it seems as if this novel could
have been called the ‘sun worshippers’ as there are many paeons to the cosmic
power of the sun. The sun is the “power base” (372), it is a “wordless friend”
(86), the “universal proletarian” (253). At one point, Chepurny, in responding
to the need for theses to be sent to the Provincial Capital so as temporarily
absolve Chevengur from suspicion, offers a treatise on something approaching
primitive communism: “The sun’s your first theses, water’s your second and the
soil’s the third.” (260) It is as if Platonov has had access to those of Marx’s
writings on the Rural Commune and the transition from feudalism that only became
available ten years after Paltonov had finished writing this novel:
“Appropriation of the natural condition of labour, of the earth as the
original instrument of labour, both laboratory and repository of its raw
materials; however, appropriation not by means of labour, but as the preliminary
condition of labour.”[23]
In light of this it is as if the Chevengurians, as not so much hunters but
gatherers, are not compelled to work by “objective conditions,” but are
immersed
in the “earth as a natural condition of production,”[24]
as the “self-seeding of nature.” (174) Chepurny fantasises about an
“International of Cereal and Flowers” that could nourish the poor “without the
interference of labour and exploitation” (325), without the encumbrance of
production quotas. In Chevengur is it that the boundlessness of the steppe, in
giving room to their querulous desires, has shifted the existential pressure of
self-preservation into an elsewhere, a place of new amalgamated passions, where
there is no need to work?
This is
not to suggest that there is neither activity nor praxis in Chevengur. Yes,
there are neither factories nor mechanised agriculture in its environs, and
likewise there is neither wage-labour nor money. So, what is the nature of the
‘doing’ in Chevengur? One could say
what is practiced here is Platonov’s idea of a proletarian art that makes
neither sculptures, nor paintings, but which makes labour and its ‘products’
itself a creative endeavour in an almost Fourierist sense in that, by and large,
as a kind of ‘living labour’, it coincides with the fulfilment of passions
towards others and the community at large. This re-rendering of labour often as
care-work and conscientiousness towards others comes to take on the hue of what,
many decades later, may be called ‘affective labour’ or, in Marx’s sense, a
labour that is satisfying in that, no longer reliant on property-relations it
ceases to be an alienated labour and becomes one that is carried out as a “free
expression” between members of a species.[25]
This is seen throughout Chevengur. Under the “objective conditions” of
Chevengur, labour becomes the epitome of a selflessness that brings not
self-loss but self-presence by means of the species-being of another: “I thought
you were chopping for yourselves – but if it’s for someone else, that’s another
matter. It’s not labour, it’s the gift of help.” (404) Whereas in the Rural
Commune Marx could speak of production for use rather than production for
exchange, in Chevengur there is no concept of use-value: “But we’re not working
for use. We’re working for one another […] It was the bourgeoisie wanted labour
to be of use […]” (441) What could be more useless than working on messthetic
objects? This is another activity that takes-off in Chevengur: “The artist had
sculpted this monument to his chosen dear comrade with an inspired tenderness
and the roughness of unskilled labour.” (459-60) This is another aspect in this
makeshift ontology of communism: the subject objectively offers herself by means
of the now revealed sensuous labour of an object that, in not existing for sale,
becomes, as Serbinov comments “without falsehood and without exploitation.”
(460) Serbinov is a character who has come to carry out an ‘audit’ on Chevengur
and if ever gets round to writing his report he may have suggested that
exchange-value has similarly ceased: exchange in Chevengur is closer to a
gift-giving and potlatch – “labour at the manufacture of gifts” (465) – and thus
transforms value from its economic sense as abstract labour into something more
akin to the communist values of social recipocrity.
One
character who ends ignominiously and breaks the affinal bond is Prokofy. It is
he, the go-to intellectual, who begins to make up an inventory of the ‘property’
in Chevengur and hopes to appropriate it and trade it in somehow. Prior to this,
and as part of the reader’s introduction to Chevengur, one of the pastimes on
the only allotted work day (Saturday), is to move the houses and structures
around so that they never occupy the same space. In a foreshadowing of, amongst
other blueprints, Constant’s New Babylon project, the very town is errant
and property never becomes static enough to be owned. For early Marx
property-relations mark a growing occlusion of human-relations, a means of
establishing individualising social differentiation by instilling private needs
that, becoming an accumulative urge, led to the dissolution of, for instance,
the Rural Commune. As a character in Chevegnur offers: “When property
lies between people, they calmly expend their powers on concerns about that
property, but when there is nothing between people, then they choose not to part
from one another.” (329) The
values reiterated across the novel is that communism is, in part, the
enshrining of non-familial but affinal social relations that, in becoming a
human need over and above property, veer very close to Fourier’s notion of the
celadonic: “The mere existence of another necessary person […] is enough
to make them into a source of heartfelt peace and endurance, the other’s highest
substance and the wealth of his indigence.” (433) Such an attentive tenderness
towards others, such a “general mutuality [bringing] comfort to any unexpected
soul” (323) may be what Platonov means by ‘more than religion’ in that rather
than the Chevengurians wilfully alienating themselves to a ‘higher power’ they
have, in establishing a “Noughtocracy” (115) – with all its suggestive
connotations of zero-profit and thus of lives lived beyond (re) numeration and
the extraction of surplus value –
brought about a version of primitive communism that Camatte defined as a social
form in which the “motion of value is yet to begin […] and the individual is not
yet a worker.”
[26]
Feel-Communism
We have
suggested that the Chevengurians are ‘organic intellectuals’, those that
practice an auto-theorisation in which lived experience and a sense of personal
history interact with concepts and ideas, but, just as rising social
differentiation came to instaurate power-relations in the Rural Commune,
something troubles thought that maybe prevents it from turning into a form of
knowledge that can too easily become a means of intellectual domination. In
Freudian terms the primary process of the unconscious, with its
transmission-belt to
feelings and affects that outstrip language, is that which interrupts
the enshrining of conscious
thought. The Chevengurians grapple with this throughout the book. One
character talks of a “rising lake of feeling,” (178) another describes thinking
“without clear thoughts,” (51) yet another disputes any notion of a thought that
could accumulate into knowledge: “many of his feelings remained unspoken and
were transformed into mute yearning.” (232) In this light the Chevengurians are
each struggling, albeit apart, with an existential discomfort, an “appetitive
process” (as Lacan once termed desire), that the institutions of state communism
cannot abate. Chepurny intuits this and as he puts it after Kirey asserts that
communism is the brain child of clever people: “But why, I ask you now, do you
keep needing to know? You need to feel communism […]” (324) This
seemingly most unintellectual of urgings may very well be another ontological
aspect of communism if we settle on a seemingly simple phrase of Marx’s:
“sensuous consciousness.”
[27] Here, in few syllables, Marx seems to
collide thought and feeling together, but what is paramount is that such a
sensuous thought is articulatable not in a treatise, but as the
social-conscience that the Chevengurians feel for any “citizen at all.” (222)
Does this not alter what it means to ‘think’? Does this not create a
singularisation of thought by means of the commune as a whole? Platonov: “What
Sasha meant by thinking was not the consideration of ideas but the constant
imagination of beloved objects – and his main beloved objects were now the
people of Chevengur.” (406) Here we have something akin to Camatte’s take on the
Gemeinwesen: an internal social life. Or. Communism as a substantial
feeling.
If Marx
once offered communism as “the positive suppression of private property as human
self-estrangement,”
[28] then, bearing in mind the capitalist
presupposition of the separation of the public from the private, we would be
advised to extend this notion of property to that of the psyche. Such an
ontological exploration of communism infers that the psyche as a form of
‘personal property’ be critiqued. Just as any commodity includes the hidden
dimension of labour, the albeit reified ‘property’ of the individual psyche
contains an occluded social dynamism (a work of auto-theorisation) that often
goes unsaid. Often this potential psychical exchange, as an abolition of
‘private property,’ remains unspoken because it is the very webwork of
‘self-estrangement’ (an uncensored primary process) that lies there. This is the
stuff of mental ill-health and just as many of Platonov’s characters could be
described as melancholics, for whom sadness is a substance, there is also an
inchoate sense in which the characters urge an overcoming of this split between
private and public. Lane offers that utopias often fall short because they do
not take into account this “common inner world”
[29] and make an abreactive space for it.
Platonov’s characters seem to be in a restless search for such a making-common
of psychical materials. One character says that the troubles of life should be
shared out equally, (292) another that “we must set about the deliberate
organisation of grief.” (259) It is telling that Platonov has this character
immediately defer his own suggestion to the next day for this is an immense and
almost unthinkable task that lies at the horizon of communism.[30]
It would have been very intriguing in the novel if different characters felt
this absence of ‘psychical exchange’ without sharing it between themselves. As
it is, it falls to Chepurny: “Their inner beings […] still lived separately and
were helplessly afflicted by suffering. People, then, could not be truly united
– and this was why Gopner and Kopionkin could not detect the presence of
communism; it had not yet become an intermediary substance between the inner
beings of the proletarians.” (400) This intermediary substance, this secular
ectoplasm, is opaque affect.[31]
What of
this intermediary substance? Are we talking of the affect attunement of the
parent-child relationship? Of communicative capacities that proceed outside of
language? As Platonov ruefully writes: “[Kopionkin] had been riding beside Sasha
Dvanov. When he began to feel sad, Sasha had felt sad too – and their sadness
had reached out to each other, met, and stopped halfway.” (360) Whilst this
resonates with Chepurny’s feel for the lack of ‘psychical exchange’ in their
practice of communism, we are nonetheless witness as to how the Rural Commune
that is Chevengur seems to be functioning well enough for the Chevengurians to
declare the RevCom as unnecessary. As well as this, and as is also demonstrated
in Platonov’s The Foundation Pit whose navvies build a collective farm,
there seems to be a gradual coming together around a unified purpose without
this purpose being declared. This is seen in the outbreak of co-operative and
unalienated labour, a tacit sense of unity that spreads throughout Chevengur not
by means of decree but through gestural example: “Each other was working
not for himself, but for someone else; each had seen Gopner mend the roof above
Yakov Titych.” (410) Outside the edicts and planning of the RevCom, the
Chevengurians (most tellingly: the ideology-resistant others) seem to be
putting into action the “anti-commandments” (168) of the anarchist Pashintsev
who lives “without the least leadership” (171) and whom Dvanov encounters on his
travels and from whom he takes the advice to “look for communism amid the
spontaneous initiative of the population.” (95) Such spontaneity, much maligned
by the Bolshevik authorities, may well be less unthinking than is presumed as it
perhaps belies the almost mystical notion of an extra sensory perception that,
as with the incursions of music that Paltonov depicts as coming as if from
nowhere, acts to form a sense of the group as perceptually responsive on a
different perhaps more poetic level. The old Bolshevik, Vekofy offers: “It was
as if his senses were located some way in front of him, allowing him to
understand any phenomenon even without close proximity to it.” (318) We may very
well be wandering into a spiritual zone, an egregorian quarter,[32]
but one that is replete with that “feeling-thinking”[33]
often commonly understood as maternal intuition.
November-December 2024
[1]
Andrey Platonov, Chevengur, Harvill Secker, 2023, p.534. Further
citations from this book appear in brackets.
[2]
Jean-Pierre Voyer, Reich: How to Use, Bureau of Public Secrets
1973.
[3]
A Marxist as respected as Karl Korsch offered: “Beneath the surface of
this immediate reality there lies a profound dimension, more difficult
to grasp, but just as real; a dimension that embraces not only the given
reality itself, but also its continual alteration […] its transition to
new forms of life.” See his Three Essays on Marxism, Monthly
Review Press Classics 1971, p.57.
[4]
Tara Lane, Andrey Platonov: The Forgotten Dream of the Revolution,
Lexington 2018, p.30. Accessed at Memory of the World.
[5]
“You see only our errors and cannot understand that we are not erring
but searching. We are coming from below […] There is no ugliness for the
living.” Platonov, cited by Lane, ibid, p.28.
[6]
Richard Stites, Revolutionary Dreams: Utopian Visions and
Experimental Life in the Russian Revolution, Oxford University Press
1989, p.211. Accessed at Memory of the World. These unfamiliar “signs
and names” can lead us in another direction. See below.
[7]
Karl Marx, ‘Letter to Vera Zasulich – The ‘Second’ Draft,’ in Teodor
Shanin, Late Marx and the Russian Road, Routledge & Keegan Paul,
1983, p.112. This is Marx’s emphasis.
[8]
Jacques Camatte, Community and Communism in Russia, London 1978,
p.25.
[9]
Nicolay Chernychevsky, ‘A Critique of Philosophical Prejudices against
Communal Ownership’ (1859) in Shanin, ibid, p.182.
[10]
See Paul Frölich,
Rosa Luxemburg: Ideas in Action, Pluto 1972, p.7.
[11]
Camatte, ibid, p.24. Here Camatte is paraphrasing Pavel Miliukov as
cited by Franco Venturi, Roots of Revolution, Wiedenfeld &
Nicholson, 1960.
[12]
This is hinted at by Luxemburg when she writes “the very physical
existence of the working class still had to be extracted from the dry
language of official industrial statistics; every mathematical
proletarian […] had to be fought over in heated polemics.” Quoted by
Frölich,
ibid, p.17. Author’s emphasis. Frölich
does not include a citation for this statement.
[13]
Marx, ‘Letter to Vera Zasulich – The ‘First’ Draft’, ibid, p.108.
[14]
Platonov, ‘Builders of the Country’, as cited by Robert Chandler in the
footnotes to Chevengur, ibid, p.533. In ‘About Love’ Platonov
writes “since communism and religion are incompatible, then, in place of
religion we must give the people not less than religion but more than
religion.” Ibid, p.533. This yearning for “political spirituality”
(Foucault) is perhaps articulated at a distance from communist theory:
in the novels of Clarice Lispector, Pier Paolo Pasolini, Jean Genet,
etc. See also Mohammed Abdou, Anarchism and Islam: Relationships and
Resonances, Pluto 2022.
[15]
The theme of parental domination and the psychical harm done to children
often recurs in Camatte’s later writings via a close reading of Alice
Miller and Elena Belotti. See especially ‘Inversion and the Rupture in
Continuity’ (2018) at
https://illwill.com/inversion-and-the-rupture-in-continuity.
[16]
Notions of ‘future persons’ mainly expressed by the phrase ‘New Soviet
Man (sic)’ were prevalent in this period. Stites cites Lunacharsky:
“Communal life is based not on compulsion and the need to herd together
for mere self-preservation, but on a free and natural merging of
personalities into superpersonal entities.” Stites, ibid, p207.
[17]
In ‘A Story about Many Interesting Things’, Platonov has a character
say: “People trade knowledge like goods […] Knowledge has become a
property; a kind of goods. He who possesses it can trade in it and grow
rich.” Cited by Robert Chandler, ibid, p.542.
[18]
Stites, ibid, p.223.
[19]
Stites cites N.V. Ustrylov: “The revolution is merciless not only toward
those who lag behind it but also toward those that run ahead of it.”
Ibid, p.225. Ustrylov is described as “leading pioneer of National
Bolshevism who was executed during the Stalinst purges.” (wiki)
[20]
Hegel, cited by Lawrence Kadar in his Introduction to The
Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx, Internationaal Instituut voor
Sociale Geschiedenis Amsterdam, 1974, p.74.
[21]
Who is to say that a new language wouldn’t emerge from a meeting of the
illiterate and the literate: “Language itself is just as much the
product of a community, as […] it is the existence of a community; it
is, as it were, the communal being speaking for itself.” See Karl Marx,
Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations, Lawrence & Wishart, 1978,
p.88.
[22]
Platonov’s polyvocal and polychronic rendition of communism seems
suited to the notion of an ‘historic party’ as glossed by Camatte: “The
party is this immense force above generations […] it represents the
human species […] it is the consciousness of the species.” See Camatte,
Origin and Function of the Party Form, London 1977, p.20.
[23]
Marx, ibid, p.88. Marx’s emphasis.
[24]
op cit, p.97.
[25]
Marx, ‘Notes on James Mill’ in Early Writings, Pelican 1975,
p.277. Again, as this essay was first published in German in 1932,
Platonov would have no knowledge of it.
[26]
Camatte, Community and Communism in Russia, ibid, p.19.
[27]
Marx, ibid, p.385.
[28]
Marx, ibid, p.348.
[29]
Lane, ibid, p.131.
[30]
Lane has articulated this difficulty extremely well when she also picks
up on this slipstream in Platonov’s writings: “He
shows us again and again how shared existence lives on in our inner
world in a way that cannot be grasped according to the parameters of
subjectivity because existence in common consists in being outside of
ourselves within ourselves.” See Lane, ibid, op cit.
[31]
For ‘opaque affect’ see my ‘Is there an Affective Class?’ at
https://illwill.com/is-there-an-affective-class
[32]
“An egregore is a non-physical entity that is created by the collective
thoughts and emotions of a group of people.” (wiki) I first came across
this word as used by Ivan Chtcheglov in ‘Formulary for a New Urbanism’,
Ecrits Retrouvés
Editions Allia 2006, p.15. The passage in which this word appears is one
of several omitted from the more well-known version edited by Guy Debord
for International Situationniste, No.1, 1958. See also my ‘Letter
from Even Further Afar’, unpublished, 2024.
[33]
Clarice Lispector, A Breath of Life, Penguin 2012, p.67. In
The Foundation Pit, Platonov has one of his characters say: “Suppose
that reason is indeed a synthesis of all feeling […]” Harvill 1996,
p.144.
[34]
Lea Melandri, Love and Violence: The Vexatious Factors of
Civilization, SUNY Press 2011, p.88.
[35]
Lea Melandri, ‘Personal Modification is not the Revolution’ see
https://illwill.com/personal-modification-is-not-revolution